To install click the Add extension button. That's it.

The source code for the WIKI 2 extension is being checked by specialists of the Mozilla Foundation, Google, and Apple. You could also do it yourself at any point in time.

4,5
Kelly Slayton
Congratulations on this excellent venture
 what a great idea!
Alexander Grigorievskiy
I use WIKI 2 every day and almost forgot how the original Wikipedia looks like.
What we do. Every page goes through several hundred of perfecting techniques; in live mode. Quite the same Wikipedia. Just better.
.
Leo
Newton
Brights
Milds

Martin's axiom

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

In the mathematical field of set theory, Martin's axiom, introduced by Donald A. Martin and Robert M. Solovay,[1] is a statement that is independent of the usual axioms of ZFC set theory. It is implied by the continuum hypothesis, but it is consistent with ZFC and the negation of the continuum hypothesis. Informally, it says that all cardinals less than the cardinality of the continuum, 𝔠, behave roughly like â„”0. The intuition behind this can be understood by studying the proof of the Rasiowa–Sikorski lemma. It is a principle that is used to control certain forcing arguments.

YouTube Encyclopedic

  • 1/5
    Views:
    469
    62 034
    136 002
    16 580
    2 388
  • Martin's axiom
  • What's so wrong with the Axiom of Choice ?
  • The unsolvable problem that launched a revolution in set theory
  • Axiom of Choice and Zorn's Lemma
  • 05 Forcing axioms, finite conditions and some more by Mirna DĆŸamonja

Transcription

Statement

For a cardinal number Îș, define the following statement:

MA(Îș)
For any partial order P satisfying the countable chain condition (hereafter ccc) and any set D = { Di }i∈I of dense subsets of P such that |D| ≀ Îș, there is a filter F on P such that F ∩ Di is non-empty for every Di ∈ D.

In this case (for application of ccc), an antichain is a subset A of P such that any two distinct members of A are incompatible (two elements are said to be compatible if there exists a common element below both of them in the partial order). This differs from, for example, the notion of antichain in the context of trees.

MA(â„”0) is provable in ZFC and known as the Rasiowa–Sikorski lemma.

MA(2â„”0) is false: [0, 1] is a separable compact Hausdorff space, and so (P, the poset of open subsets under inclusion, is) ccc. But now consider the following two 𝔠-size sets of dense sets in P: no x ∈ [0, 1] is isolated, and so each x defines the dense subset { S | x ∉ S }. And each r ∈ (0, 1], defines the dense subset { S | diam(S) < r }. The two sets combined are also of size 𝔠, and a filter meeting both must simultaneously avoid all points of [0, 1] while containing sets of arbitrarily small diameter. But a filter F containing sets of arbitrarily small diameter must contain a point in ⋂F by compactness. (See also § Equivalent forms of MA(Îș).)

Martin's axiom is then that MA(Îș) holds for every Îș for which it could:

Martin's axiom (MA)
MA(Îș) holds for every Îș < 𝔠.

Equivalent forms of MA(Îș)

The following statements are equivalent to MA(Îș):

  • If X is a compact Hausdorff topological space that satisfies the ccc then X is not the union of Îș or fewer nowhere dense subsets.
  • If P is a non-empty upwards ccc poset and Y is a set of cofinal subsets of P with |Y| ≀ Îș then there is an upwards-directed set A such that A meets every element of Y.
  • Let A be a non-zero ccc Boolean algebra and F a set of subsets of A with |F| ≀ Îș. Then there is a boolean homomorphism Ï†â€Ż: A → Z/2Z such that for every X ∈ F, there is either an a ∈ X with φ(a) = 1 or there is an upper bound b ∈ X with φ(b) = 0.

Consequences

Martin's axiom has a number of other interesting combinatorial, analytic and topological consequences:

  • The union of Îș or fewer null sets in an atomless σ-finite Borel measure on a Polish space is null. In particular, the union of Îș or fewer subsets of R of Lebesgue measure 0 also has Lebesgue measure 0.
  • A compact Hausdorff space X with |X| < 2Îș is sequentially compact, i.e., every sequence has a convergent subsequence.
  • No non-principal ultrafilter on N has a base of cardinality less than Îș.
  • Equivalently for any x ∈ ÎČN\N we have 𝜒(x) ≄ Îș, where 𝜒 is the character of x, and so 𝜒(ÎČN) ≄ Îș.
  • MA(â„”1) implies that a product of ccc topological spaces is ccc (this in turn implies there are no Suslin lines).
  • MA + CH implies that there exists a Whitehead group that is not free; Shelah used this to show that the Whitehead problem is independent of ZFC.

Further development

References

  1. ^ Martin, Donald A.; Solovay, Robert M. (1970). "Internal Cohen extensions". Ann. Math. Logic. 2 (2): 143–178. doi:10.1016/0003-4843(70)90009-4. MR 0270904.
  2. ^ Davis, Sheldon W. (2005). Topology. McGraw Hill. p. 29. ISBN 0-07-291006-2.

Further reading

This page was last edited on 8 April 2024, at 10:33
Basis of this page is in Wikipedia. Text is available under the CC BY-SA 3.0 Unported License. Non-text media are available under their specified licenses. WikipediaÂź is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc. WIKI 2 is an independent company and has no affiliation with Wikimedia Foundation.