To install click the Add extension button. That's it.

The source code for the WIKI 2 extension is being checked by specialists of the Mozilla Foundation, Google, and Apple. You could also do it yourself at any point in time.

4,5
Kelly Slayton
Congratulations on this excellent venture… what a great idea!
Alexander Grigorievskiy
I use WIKI 2 every day and almost forgot how the original Wikipedia looks like.
Live Statistics
English Articles
Improved in 24 Hours
Added in 24 Hours
Languages
Recent
Show all languages
What we do. Every page goes through several hundred of perfecting techniques; in live mode. Quite the same Wikipedia. Just better.
.
Leo
Newton
Brights
Milds

Sieve (category theory)

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

In category theory, a branch of mathematics, a sieve is a way of choosing arrows with a common codomain. It is a categorical analogue of a collection of open subsets of a fixed open set in topology. In a Grothendieck topology, certain sieves become categorical analogues of open covers in topology. Sieves were introduced by Giraud (1964) in order to reformulate the notion of a Grothendieck topology.

YouTube Encyclopedic

  • 1/3
    Views:
    2 160
    9 426
    22 744
  • Sites and Sheaves Mainline 1
  • Mod-03 Lec-10 Morphological Characterization: Particle size distributions
  • What is Shor's factoring algorithm?

Transcription

Definition

Let C be a category, and let c be an object of C. A sieve on c is a subfunctor of Hom(−, c), i.e., for all objects c′ of C, S(c′) ⊆ Hom(c′, c), and for all arrows f:c″→c′, S(f) is the restriction of Hom(f, c), the pullback by f (in the sense of precomposition, not of fiber products), to S(c′); see the next section, below.

Put another way, a sieve is a collection S of arrows with a common codomain that satisfies the condition, "If g:c′→c is an arrow in S, and if f:c″→c′ is any other arrow in C, then gf is in S." Consequently, sieves are similar to right ideals in ring theory or filters in order theory.

Pullback of sieves

The most common operation on a sieve is pullback. Pulling back a sieve S on c by an arrow f:c′→c gives a new sieve f*S on c′. This new sieve consists of all the arrows in S that factor through c′.

There are several equivalent ways of defining f*S. The simplest is:

For any object d of C, f*S(d) = { g:dc′ | fg ∈ S(d)}

A more abstract formulation is:

f*S is the image of the fibered product S×Hom(−, c)Hom(−, c′) under the natural projection S×Hom(−, c)Hom(−, c′)→Hom(−, c′).

Here the map Hom(−, c′)→Hom(−, c) is Hom(−, f), the push forward by f.

The latter formulation suggests that we can also take the image of S×Hom(−, c)Hom(−, c′) under the natural map to Hom(−, c). This will be the image of f*S under composition with f. For each object d of C, this sieve will consist of all arrows fg, where g:dc′ is an arrow of f*S(d). In other words, it consists of all arrows in S that can be factored through f.

If we denote by ∅c the empty sieve on c, that is, the sieve for which ∅(d) is always the empty set, then for any f:c′→c, f*c is ∅c. Furthermore, f*Hom(−, c) = Hom(−, c′).

Properties of sieves

Let S and S′ be two sieves on c. We say that SS′ if for all objects c′ of C, S(c′) ⊆ S′(c′). For all objects d of C, we define (SS′)(d) to be S(d) ∪ S′(d) and (SS′)(d) to be S(d) ∩ S′(d). We can clearly extend this definition to infinite unions and intersections as well.

If we define SieveC(c) (or Sieve(c) for short) to be the set of all sieves on c, then Sieve(c) becomes partially ordered under ⊆. It is easy to see from the definition that the union or intersection of any family of sieves on c is a sieve on c, so Sieve(c) is a complete lattice.

A Grothendieck topology is a collection of sieves subject to certain properties. These sieves are called covering sieves. The set of all covering sieves on an object c is a subset J(c) of Sieve(c). J(c) satisfies several properties in addition to those required by the definition:

  • If S and S′ are sieves on c, SS′, and SJ(c), then S′ ∈ J(c).
  • Finite intersections of elements of J(c) are in J(c).

Consequently, J(c) is also a distributive lattice, and it is cofinal in Sieve(c).

References

  • Artin, Michael; Alexandre Grothendieck; Jean-Louis Verdier, eds. (1972). Séminaire de Géométrie Algébrique du Bois Marie - 1963-64 - Théorie des topos et cohomologie étale des schémas - (SGA 4) - vol. 1. Lecture notes in mathematics (in French). Vol. 269. Berlin; New York: Springer-Verlag. xix+525. doi:10.1007/BFb0081551. ISBN 978-3-540-05896-0.
  • Giraud, Jean (1964), "Analysis situs", Séminaire Bourbaki, 1962/63. Fasc. 3, Paris: Secrétariat mathématique, MR 0193122
  • Pedicchio, Maria Cristina; Tholen, Walter, eds. (2004). Categorical foundations. Special topics in order, topology, algebra, and sheaf theory. Encyclopedia of Mathematics and Its Applications. Vol. 97. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-83414-7. Zbl 1034.18001.
This page was last edited on 28 April 2024, at 07:29
Basis of this page is in Wikipedia. Text is available under the CC BY-SA 3.0 Unported License. Non-text media are available under their specified licenses. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc. WIKI 2 is an independent company and has no affiliation with Wikimedia Foundation.