To install click the Add extension button. That's it.

The source code for the WIKI 2 extension is being checked by specialists of the Mozilla Foundation, Google, and Apple. You could also do it yourself at any point in time.

4,5
Kelly Slayton
Congratulations on this excellent venture… what a great idea!
Alexander Grigorievskiy
I use WIKI 2 every day and almost forgot how the original Wikipedia looks like.
Live Statistics
English Articles
Improved in 24 Hours
Added in 24 Hours
What we do. Every page goes through several hundred of perfecting techniques; in live mode. Quite the same Wikipedia. Just better.
.
Leo
Newton
Brights
Milds

Naive Set Theory (book)

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

See also Naive set theory for the mathematical topic.
First edition

Naive Set Theory is a mathematics textbook by Paul Halmos providing an undergraduate introduction to set theory.[1] Originally published by Van Nostrand in 1960,[2] it was reprinted in the Springer-Verlag Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics series in 1974.[3]

While the title states that it is naive, which is usually taken to mean without axioms, the book does introduce all the axioms of ZFC set theory (except the Axiom of Foundation), and gives correct and rigorous definitions for basic objects.[2][4] Where it differs from a "true" axiomatic set theory book is its character: there are no discussions of axiomatic minutiae, and there is next to nothing about advanced topics like large cardinals. Instead, it tries to be intelligible to someone who has never thought about set theory before.

Halmos later stated that it was the fastest book he wrote, taking about six months, and that the book "wrote itself".[5]

YouTube Encyclopedic

  • 1/5
    Views:
    1 015
    141 762
    3 183
    1 485
    2 131
  • Naïve Type Theory by Thorsten Altenkirch (University of Nottingham, UK)
  • Lecture 10 - Sets
  • Introduction to Number Sets and Counting Principle
  • Topology Without Tears - Video 2c - Infinite Set Theory
  • Basics of Set Theory - Chapter 2 pretest review

Transcription

Absence of the Axiom of Foundation

As noted above, the book omits the Axiom of Foundation (also known as the Axiom of Regularity). Halmos repeatedly dances around the issue of whether or not a set can contain itself.

  • p. 1: "a set may also be an element of some other set" (emphasis added)
  • p. 3: "is ever true? It is certainly not true of any reasonable set that anyone has ever seen."
  • p. 6: " ... unlikely, but not obviously impossible"

But Halmos does let us prove that there are certain sets that cannot contain themselves.

  • p. 44: Halmos lets us prove that . For if , then − {} would still be a successor set, because ≠ ∅ and is not the successor of any natural number. But is not a subset of − {}, contradicting the definition of as a subset of every successor set.
  • p. 47: Halmos proves the lemma that "no natural number is a subset of any of its elements." This lets us prove that no natural number can contain itself. For if , where is a natural number, then , which contradicts the lemma.
  • p. 75: "An ordinal number is defined as a well ordered set such that for all in ; here is, as before, the initial segment < }." The well ordering is defined as follows: if and are elements of an ordinal number , then < means (pp. 75-76). By his choice of the symbol < instead of ≤, Halmos implies that the well ordering < is strict (pp. 55-56). This definition of < makes it impossible to have , where is an element of an ordinal number. That's because means < , which implies (because < is strict), which is impossible.
  • p. 75: the above definition of an ordinal number also makes it impossible to have , where is an ordinal number. That's because implies = s(). This gives us = s() = < }, which implies < , which implies (because < is strict), which is impossible.

Errata

  • p. 4, line 18: “Cain and Abel” should be “Seth, Cain and Abel”.
  • p. 30, line 10: "x onto y" should be "x into y".
  • p. 73, line 19: "for each z in X" should be "for each a in X".
  • p. 75, line 3: "if and only if x ∈ F(n)" should be "if and only if x = {b: S(n, b)}".
  • p, 66, line 16: "Consider, for example, the set E of all those pairs (a,b) for which (1,1) <= (a,b); the set E has (1,1) for its least element.": the statement is not true, since (2,2) <= (1,1). In fact (2x2+1)x2^1 = 10 <= (2x1+1)x2^2 = 12.

See also

Bibliography

  • Halmos, Paul, Naive Set Theory. Princeton, NJ: D. Van Nostrand Company, 1960. Reprinted by Springer-Verlag, New York, 1974. ISBN 0-387-90092-6 (Springer-Verlag edition). Reprinted by Martino Fine Books, 2011. ISBN 978-1-61427-131-4 (Paperback edition); 2017 Dover reprint ISBN 9780486814872

References

  1. ^ Review of Naive Set Theory by H. Mirkil (April 1961), American Mathematical Monthly 68 (4): 392, doi:10.2307/2311615.
  2. ^ a b Review of Naive Set Theory, L. Rieger, MR0114756.
  3. ^ MR0453532
  4. ^ Review of Naive Set Theory, Alfons Borgers (July 1969), Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (2): 308, doi:10.2307/2271138.
  5. ^ Ewing, John H.; Gehring, Frederick W., eds. (1991), Paul Halmos: celebrating 50 years of mathematics, Springer-Verlag, Interview of Halmos with Donald J. Albers, p. 16, ISBN 0-387-97509-8.
This page was last edited on 13 November 2023, at 17:44
Basis of this page is in Wikipedia. Text is available under the CC BY-SA 3.0 Unported License. Non-text media are available under their specified licenses. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc. WIKI 2 is an independent company and has no affiliation with Wikimedia Foundation.