To install click the Add extension button. That's it.

The source code for the WIKI 2 extension is being checked by specialists of the Mozilla Foundation, Google, and Apple. You could also do it yourself at any point in time.

4,5
Kelly Slayton
Congratulations on this excellent venture… what a great idea!
Alexander Grigorievskiy
I use WIKI 2 every day and almost forgot how the original Wikipedia looks like.
Live Statistics
English Articles
Improved in 24 Hours
Added in 24 Hours
What we do. Every page goes through several hundred of perfecting techniques; in live mode. Quite the same Wikipedia. Just better.
.
Leo
Newton
Brights
Milds

Disjunctive syllogism

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Disjunctive syllogism
TypeRule of inference
FieldPropositional calculus
StatementIf is true or is true and is false, then is true.
Symbolic statement

In classical logic, disjunctive syllogism[1][2] (historically known as modus tollendo ponens (MTP),[3] Latin for "mode that affirms by denying")[4] is a valid argument form which is a syllogism having a disjunctive statement for one of its premises.[5][6]

An example in English:

  1. I will choose soup or I will choose salad.
  2. I will not choose soup.
  3. Therefore, I will choose salad.

YouTube Encyclopedic

  • 1/3
    Views:
    51 795
    3 312
    740
  • Logic 101 (#29): Disjunctive Syllogism
  • Propositional Logic - Disjunctive Syllogism
  • Introduction into Logic | Disjunctive Syllogism

Transcription

Propositional logic

In propositional logic, disjunctive syllogism (also known as disjunction elimination and or elimination, or abbreviated ∨E),[7][8][9][10] is a valid rule of inference. If it is known that at least one of two statements is true, and that it is not the former that is true; we can infer that it has to be the latter that is true. Equivalently, if P is true or Q is true and P is false, then Q is true. The name "disjunctive syllogism" derives from its being a syllogism, a three-step argument, and the use of a logical disjunction (any "or" statement.) For example, "P or Q" is a disjunction, where P and Q are called the statement's disjuncts. The rule makes it possible to eliminate a disjunction from a logical proof. It is the rule that

where the rule is that whenever instances of "", and "" appear on lines of a proof, "" can be placed on a subsequent line.

Disjunctive syllogism is closely related and similar to hypothetical syllogism, which is another rule of inference involving a syllogism. It is also related to the law of noncontradiction, one of the three traditional laws of thought.

Formal notation

For a logical system that validates it, the disjunctive syllogism may be written in sequent notation as

where is a metalogical symbol meaning that is a syntactic consequence of , and .

It may be expressed as a truth-functional tautology or theorem in the object language of propositional logic as

where , and are propositions expressed in some formal system.

Natural language examples

Here is an example:

  1. It is red or it is blue.
  2. It is not blue.
  3. Therefore, it is red.

Here is another example:

  1. The breach is a safety violation, or it is not subject to fines.
  2. The breach is not a safety violation.
  3. Therefore, it is not subject to fines.

Strong form

Modus tollendo ponens can be made stronger by using exclusive disjunction instead of inclusive disjunction as a premise:

Related argument forms

Unlike modus ponens and modus ponendo tollens, with which it should not be confused, disjunctive syllogism is often not made an explicit rule or axiom of logical systems, as the above arguments can be proven with a combination of reductio ad absurdum and disjunction elimination.

Other forms of syllogism include:

Disjunctive syllogism holds in classical propositional logic and intuitionistic logic, but not in some paraconsistent logics.[11]

See also

References

  1. ^ Copi, Irving M.; Cohen, Carl (2005). Introduction to Logic. Prentice Hall. p. 362.
  2. ^ Hurley, Patrick (1991). A Concise Introduction to Logic 4th edition. Wadsworth Publishing. pp. 320–1. ISBN 9780534145156.
  3. ^ Lemmon, Edward John. 2001. Beginning Logic. Taylor and Francis/CRC Press, p. 61.
  4. ^ Stone, Jon R. (1996). Latin for the Illiterati: Exorcizing the Ghosts of a Dead Language. London: Routledge. p. 60. ISBN 0-415-91775-1.
  5. ^ Hurley
  6. ^ Copi and Cohen
  7. ^ Sanford, David Hawley. 2003. If P, Then Q: Conditionals and the Foundations of Reasoning. London, UK: Routledge: 39
  8. ^ Hurley
  9. ^ Copi and Cohen
  10. ^ Moore and Parker
  11. ^ Chris Mortensen, Inconsistent Mathematics, Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, First published Tue Jul 2, 1996; substantive revision Thu Jul 31, 2008
This page was last edited on 3 March 2024, at 03:28
Basis of this page is in Wikipedia. Text is available under the CC BY-SA 3.0 Unported License. Non-text media are available under their specified licenses. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc. WIKI 2 is an independent company and has no affiliation with Wikimedia Foundation.