To install click the Add extension button. That's it.

The source code for the WIKI 2 extension is being checked by specialists of the Mozilla Foundation, Google, and Apple. You could also do it yourself at any point in time.

4,5
Kelly Slayton
Congratulations on this excellent venture… what a great idea!
Alexander Grigorievskiy
I use WIKI 2 every day and almost forgot how the original Wikipedia looks like.
Live Statistics
English Articles
Improved in 24 Hours
Added in 24 Hours
Languages
Recent
Show all languages
What we do. Every page goes through several hundred of perfecting techniques; in live mode. Quite the same Wikipedia. Just better.
.
Leo
Newton
Brights
Milds

Dichotomous preferences

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

In economics, dichotomous preferences (DP) are preference relations that divide the set of alternatives to two subsets: "Good" versus "Bad".

From ordinal utility perspective, DP means that for every two alternatives :[1]: 292 

From cardinal utility perspective, DP means that for each agent, there are two utility levels: low and high, and for every alternative :

A common way to let people express dichotomous preferences is using approval ballots, in which each voter can either "approve" or "reject" each alternative.

YouTube Encyclopedic

  • 1/3
    Views:
    143 503
    1 444
    314
  • Myers-Briggs Type Indicator (MBTI) | Is it a Valid Personality Test?
  • Herve Moulin: "Fair Division" Part I
  • Herve Moulin: "Fair Division" Part II

Transcription

In fair item assignment

In the context of fair item assignment, DP can be represented by a mathematical logic formula:[1]: 292  for every agent, there is a formula that describes his desired bundles. An agent is satisfied if-and-only-if he receives a bundle that satisfies the formula.

A special case of DP is single-mindedness. A single-minded agent wants a very specific bundle; he is happy if-and-only-if he receives this bundle, or any bundle that contains it. Such preferences appear in real-life, for example, in the problem of allocating classrooms to schools: each school i needs a number di of classes; the school has utility 1 if it gets all di classes in the same place and 0 otherwise. [2][3][4]

Collective choice under DP

Without money

Suppose a mechanism selects a lottery over outcomes. The utility of each agent, under this mechanism, is the probability that one of his Good outcomes is selected.

The utilitarian mechanism averages over outcomes with largest “approval”. It is Pareto efficient, strategyproof, anonymous and neutral.

It is impossible to attain these properties in addition to proportionality - giving each agent a utility of at least 1/n; or at least the fraction of good to feasible outcomes. [5] conjecture that no ex ante efficient and strategyproof mechanism guarantees a strictly positive utility to all agents, and prove a weaker statement.

With money

Suppose all agents have DP cardinal utility, where each agent is characterized by a single number - (so that ).

[6] identify a new condition, generation monotonicity, that is necessary and sufficient for implementation by a truthful mechanisms in any dichotomous domain (see Monotonicity (mechanism design)).

If such a domain satisfies a richness condition, then a weaker version of generation monotonicity, 2-generation monotonicity (equivalent to 3-cycle monotonicity), is necessary and sufficient for implementation.

This result can be used to derive the optimal mechanism in a one-sided matching problem with agents who have dichotomous types

References

  1. ^ a b Brandt, Felix; Conitzer, Vincent; Endriss, Ulle; Lang, Jérôme; Procaccia, Ariel D. (2016). Handbook of Computational Social Choice. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9781107060432. (free online version)
  2. ^ Bogomolnaia, Anna; Moulin, Herve (2004). "Random Matching Under Dichotomous Preferences". Econometrica. 72 (1): 257–279. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0262.2004.00483.x. ISSN 1468-0262.
  3. ^ Kurokawa, David; Procaccia, Ariel D.; Shah, Nisarg (2015-06-15). "Leximin Allocations in the Real World". Proceedings of the Sixteenth ACM Conference on Economics and Computation. ACM. pp. 345–362. doi:10.1145/2764468.2764490. ISBN 9781450334105. S2CID 1060279.
  4. ^ Ortega, Josué (2020-01-01). "Multi-unit assignment under dichotomous preferences". Mathematical Social Sciences. 103: 15–24. arXiv:1703.10897. doi:10.1016/j.mathsocsci.2019.11.003. ISSN 0165-4896.
  5. ^ Bogomolnaia, Anna; Moulin, Hervé; Stong, Richard (2005). "Collective choice under dichotomous preferences". Journal of Economic Theory. 122 (2): 165. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.134.211. doi:10.1016/j.jet.2004.05.005.
  6. ^ Mishra, Debasis; Roy, Souvik (2013). "Implementation in multidimensional dichotomous domains". Theoretical Economics. 8 (2): 431. doi:10.3982/TE1239. hdl:10419/150197.
This page was last edited on 5 January 2024, at 10:46
Basis of this page is in Wikipedia. Text is available under the CC BY-SA 3.0 Unported License. Non-text media are available under their specified licenses. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc. WIKI 2 is an independent company and has no affiliation with Wikimedia Foundation.