To install click the Add extension button. That's it.

The source code for the WIKI 2 extension is being checked by specialists of the Mozilla Foundation, Google, and Apple. You could also do it yourself at any point in time.

4,5
Kelly Slayton
Congratulations on this excellent venture… what a great idea!
Alexander Grigorievskiy
I use WIKI 2 every day and almost forgot how the original Wikipedia looks like.
Live Statistics
English Articles
Improved in 24 Hours
Added in 24 Hours
Languages
Recent
Show all languages
What we do. Every page goes through several hundred of perfecting techniques; in live mode. Quite the same Wikipedia. Just better.
.
Leo
Newton
Brights
Milds

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

De Corpore ("On the Body") is a 1655 book by Thomas Hobbes. As its full Latin title Elementorum philosophiae sectio prima De corpore implies, it was part of a larger work, conceived as a trilogy. De Cive had already appeared, while De Homine would be published in 1658. Hobbes had in fact been drafting De Corpore for at least ten years before its appearance, putting it aside for other matters.[1] This delay affected its reception: the approach taken seemed much less innovative than it would have done in the previous decade.[2]

YouTube Encyclopedic

  • 1/3
    Views:
    1 641
    1 835
    1 077
  • Colloquia ad linguam latinam discendam - S1E15 - De corpore humano
  • Silus et Maria ep.7 - De corpore humano (Latin4Kids)
  • Colloquia ad linguam latinam discendam - S1E16 - De Corpore Humano (pars secunda)

Transcription

Contents

Although the chosen title would suggest a work of natural philosophy, De Corpore is largely devoted to foundational matters. It consists of four sections. Part I covers logic. Part II and Part III concern “abstract bodies”: the second part is a repertoire of scientific concepts, and the third of geometry. The Chapters 16 to 20 of Part III are in fact devoted to mathematics generally, in a reductive way, and proved controversial. They proposed a kinematic foundation for geometry, which Hobbes wished to equate with mathematics; geometry itself, that is, is a “science of motion”. Hobbes here adopts ideas from Galileo Galilei and Bonaventura Cavalieri. It is in Part IV, on natural phenomena, that there is discussion of physics as such.[3][4]

Scope

Hobbes in De Corpore states that the subject of philosophy is devoted to "bodies". He clarifies this by division: in English translation, natural philosophy is concerned with concept of "natural body" (Latin: corpus naturale), while the bodies called commonwealths are the concern of "civil philosophy".[5] He then applies "body" as synonymous with substance, breaking with the scholastic tradition.[6]

Mathematical errors

Some proofs in the work being "botched", as Noel Malcolm puts it, De Corpore had a negative effect on Hobbes's scholarly reputation.[2] The inclusion of a claimed solution for squaring the circle, an apparent afterthought rather than a systematic development, led to an extended pamphlet war in the Hobbes-Wallis controversy.

Editions and translations

Hobbes supervised an English translation of De Corpore, which was published in 1656. There were some changes, and a provocative appendix Six Lessons to the Professors of Mathematics was added.[7] It has been claimed that the translation was vitiated by errors, undermining its usefulness as a guide to Hobbes's philosophy of language.[8] A planned French translation was made, but never appeared, probably because of further revision plans. No revised edition appeared until 1668, when De Corpore was included in the Opera philosophica collection of Hobbes' works.[9]

A modern translation of the first part of De Corpore is available: Thomas Hobbes, Computatio sive logica: Logic, Latin text, translation and commentary by Aloysius Martinich; edited, and with an introductory essay, by Isabel C. Hungerland and George R. Vick, New York: Abaris Books, 1981.

Critical edition of the Latin text: Thomas Hobbes, De Corpore, edited with Introduction and notes (in French) by Karl Schuhmann, Paris: Vrin, 1999.

Notes

  1. ^ Tom Sorell, The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes (1996), pp. 29-31.
  2. ^ a b Noel Malcolm (2007). Aspects of Hobbes. Oxford University Press. p. 498. ISBN 978-0-19-927540-3.
  3. ^ "Thomas Hobbes - Biography".
  4. ^ Stephen J. Finn, Thomas Hobbes and the Politics of Natural Philosophy (2006), pp. 42-5.
  5. ^ Tom Sorell (26 January 1996). The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes. Cambridge University Press. p. 57. ISBN 978-0-521-42244-4. Retrieved 16 April 2013.
  6. ^ Cornelis Hendrik Leijenhorst (2002). The Mechanisation of Aristotelianism: The Late Aristotelian Setting of Thomas Hobbes's Natural Philosophy. BRILL. p. 146. ISBN 978-90-04-11729-7. Retrieved 16 April 2013.
  7. ^ A. P. Martinich (2005). Thomas Hobbes. Routledge. pp. xiv–xv. ISBN 978-0-415-28328-1. Retrieved 16 April 2013.
  8. ^ Stephen J. Finn (4 June 2004). Thomas Hobbes and the Politics of Natural Philosophy. Continuum International Publishing Group. p. 134. ISBN 978-1-84714-331-0. Retrieved 16 April 2013.
  9. ^ Thomas Hobbes (22 September 1994). The Correspondence: Volume I: 1622-1659. Clarendon Press. p. 216 note 1 and 229 note 2. ISBN 978-0-19-824065-5. Retrieved 16 April 2013.

External links

This page was last edited on 8 April 2024, at 12:46
Basis of this page is in Wikipedia. Text is available under the CC BY-SA 3.0 Unported License. Non-text media are available under their specified licenses. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc. WIKI 2 is an independent company and has no affiliation with Wikimedia Foundation.